What is science?

Introduction

The question of what, exactly, constitutes science lies at the core of the “war” between science and religion. Many in the public arena believe that any technically-oriented analysis of the physical world constitutes science. Creationists, for instance, hold that their notion that the earth and its living things (or even the entire universe) were created out of nothing a few thousand years ago is a “scientific” theory. Similarly, leading spokespersons of the intelligent design movement, including Michael Behe and William Dembski, have asserted that their movement is primarily a scientific movement, not a religious movement, and that “intelligent design theory” deserves a place in public school classrooms [Jones2005, pg. 24-35].

Current definitions of science

Perhaps the most succinct definition of science is given by the National Academy of Science (NAS), the premier scientific association in the U.S. [NAS2008, pg. 10]: The use of evidence to construct testable explanations and predictions of natural phenomena, as well as the knowledge generated through this process.

The NAS elaborates on this definition as follows:

In science, explanations must be based on naturally occurring phenomena. Natural causes are, in principle, reproducible and therefore can be checked independently by others. If explanations are based on purported forces that are outside of nature, scientists have no way of either confirming or disproving those explanations. Any scientific explanation has to be testable — there must be possible observational consequences that could support the idea but also ones that could refute it. Unless a proposed explanation is framed in a way that some observational evidence could potentially count against it, that explanation cannot be subjected to scientific testing.

Numerous others have expressed similar views. For example, Michael Ruse, a philosopher of science who testified in the 1981 Alabama creationism case, describes science as a discipline that (1) is guided by natural law, (2) is explanatory by reference to natural law, (3) is testable against the empirical world, (4) reaches conclusions that are tentative, and (5) is falsifiable [Pennock1999, pg. 5]. Similarly, philosopher Robert Pennock emphasizes that science is based on “methodological naturalism,” which requires scientists to seek explanations based upon what can be observed, tested, replicated, and verified, and that this is a necessary “ground rule” of science today, not an optional afterthought [Jones2005, pg. 65].

Falsifiability

The importance of falsifiability in modern science, which has been emphasized by most if not all modern writers, has its roots in the writings of Karl Popper. In his influential 1959 book The Logic of Scientific Discovery, he declared [Popper1959, pg. 40-41]:

I shall certainly admit a system as empirical or scientific only if it is capable of being tested by experience. These considerations suggest that not the verifiability but the falsifiability of a system is to be taken as the criterion of demarcation. … It must be possible for an empirical scientific system to be refuted by experience.

Popper’s ideas remain highly influential in scientific research even to the present day. For example, several prominent scientists have recently expressed concern about whether it is prudent to continue pursuing string theory, given that practitioners have not yet been able to derive empirically testable consequences even after 25 years of effort. Physicist Lee Smolin, for example, writes, “A scientific theory that makes no predictions and therefore is not subject to experiment can never fail, but such a theory can never succeed either, as long as science stands for knowledge gained from rational argument borne out by evidence.” [Smolin2006, pg. 352].

However, Popper’s ideas do have some limitations, some of which were pointed out by Popper himself in his earliest works. To begin with, in most real modern-day scientific research, major theories are seldom falsified by a single experimental result. There are always questions regarding the underlying experimental design, measurement procedures, and data analysis techniques, not to mention statistical uncertainties. Often multiple follow-on studies, in some cases extending over many years, are necessary to conclusively decide the hypothesis one way or the other. For example, 13 years elapsed between 1998, when two teams of researchers discovered that the expansion of the universe is accelerating, and 2011, when the lead scientists of the two teams (Saul Perlmutter of the Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory and Brian Schmidt of the Australian national University) were awarded the Nobel Prize in physics, allowing time for these startling results to be very carefully scrutinized in reams of follow-on studies by researchers worldwide. In this sense, scientists are more like detectives, in that they must follow leads and hunches, examine evidence, and tentatively proceed with the most likely scenario. Seldom, if ever, are scientific results black-and-white from day one.

Some additional discussion of Popper’s philosophy and the notion of falsifiability are given in Postmodern.

Do creationism and intelligent design qualify as science?

The issue as to whether creationism qualifies as science was a key question in the 1981 McLean v. Arkansas Board of Education case, which challenged an Arkansas law requiring “balanced treatment for creation-science and evolution-science.” In overturning this law, U. S. District Court Judge William Overton, based on testimony from well-respected scientists and philosophers, ruled that “creation science” is not science because it asserts creation by a supernatural creator, by means of unknown processes that are outside the realm of natural law (and thus not testable or falsifiable by empirical evidence) [Overton1982].

Similarly, the issue of whether intelligent design qualifies as science came up in the 2005 Dover, Pennsylvania case. Catholic theologian/philosopher John Haught testified that the arguments advanced by intelligent design writers are not new scientific arguments, but instead harken back to at least the 13th century, when Thomas Aquinas argued that since nature appears to have a complex design, there must have been a Designer. Essentially the same argument was again advanced in the 19th century by William Paley. And although modern intelligent design authors do not publicly identify this designer with God, Haught points out that anyone familiar with Western religious thought would immediately make the connection with the Judeo-Christian God [Jones2005, pg. 25].

In the same case, scientific philosopher Robert Pennock testified that because intelligent design teaches that the features of the natural world were produced by a transcendent, immaterial, non-natural being, it is thus a religious, not a scientific movement [Jones2005, pg. 28]. It is telling that intelligent design writer Michael Behe, in his court testimony, acknowledged that the “plausibility of the argument for [intelligent design] depends upon the extent to which one believes in the existence of God.” But as Judge Jones noted in his opinion, there is no evidence “that any other scientific proposition’s validity rests on belief in God” [Jones2005, pg. 28].

One other key item of evidence noted in the Dover trial was the testimony of Barbara Forrest, who found, through her careful analysis of the intelligent design textbook Of Pandas and People, that this book was merely a lightly edited reworking of an earlier creationist text, where, for example, the words “creation,” “God,” “creationism,” and “Genesis” had been systematically replaced by less overtly religious words such as “intelligent design” and “designer.” Other than superficial changes such as this, many of the same arguments and examples were retained, almost word for word [Jones2005, pg. 32-35].

In his decision, Judge Jones further noted that the intelligent design movement had failed to gain acceptance in the scientific community. In particular, it had not generated any peer-reviewed publications, as is required of all legitimate scientific research. He ultimately concluded that intelligent design fails to meet the essential ground rules to qualify as science [Jones2005, pg. 70].

For additional background on creationism and intelligent design, see Creationism and Intelligent design. For additional details on the 1981 and 2005 court cases, see Court cases.

Conclusions

Science is a well-defined process marked by utilizing empirical evidence from the physical world to construct and develop testable, falsifiable explanations of natural phenomenal, in terms of natural laws and processes. Thus by its definition, science cannot render judgments one way or the other on the existence or nature of God, or on processes of creation that are hypothesized to lie outside the realm of natural law. What’s more, science, properly defined, can say nothing about the ultimate purpose of creation, nor can it provide any fundamental direction for ethics or morality. These questions are better pursued through the arena of religion.

But by the same token, creationism and intelligent design also lie outside the realm of science. Those who finds the precepts of these movements appealing are welcome to believe them and even to advance them in public discourse. But it is a serious mistake, both for religious believers as well as society, to argue that they are legitimate scientific theories. They are not.

Comments are closed.